CARL
SCHMITT AND
THE NEOCONSERVATIVE JUSTIFICATION FOR THE SOVEREIGNTY OF POLITICS
BY
STÅLE R. S. FINKE
Professor of Philosophy, University of Trondheim
Imagining
oneself as a member of the society of world
citizens, obligated according to the rights
of state
citizens is the
highest
idea of his destination Man can entertain. The thought cannot
be
entertained
without enthusiasm.
Immanuel
Kant
No one in the Bush
administration can be accused of being too careful in their
presentation of
and
enthusiasm for their own foreign policy. The distance between the
American and
the
European view, particularly
with regard to their perception of the
consequences of globalization
to relations between states,
is not a
case of
superficial disagreement about how to fight terror, how
to relate to
states
like Iraq or how to solve the conflict between Palestinians and
Israelis. The
so-called hawks or
neo-Conservative have prepared the ideological
ground for
American exceptionalism and a
solitary approach to world politics. What
has
been labelled Project
for a New
American
Century is a rather coherent
conservative political vision, containing
quite
detailed accounts of future
aims of foreign politics. Along with
the
political scientist Paul Wolfowitz,
there are familiar names like
Donald
Rumsfeld, Bill Kristol, Robert Kagan and Richard Perle. They
have in
common a
renewed interest in political thinking of a kind which runs counter to
the
typical European models of
justification of deliberative democracy and
universal rights in the
tradition after Immanuel
Kant. They focus
instead on a
particular reception of early modern
political philosophy in
Niccolo
Machiavelli and Thomas Hobbes. Robert Kagan states as follows:
It
is time to stop
pretending Europeans and Americans have a common world view, or even
inhabit
the same world… Europe is moving away from the focus on power
towards a
self-sufficient world of laws, trans-national negotiations and
cooperation.
They are entering a post-historical paradise of peace and fertility, a
realization of Kant’s ‘perpetual peace’. The US, however, remains
anchored in
history and exercises power in an anarchist, Hobbesian world where
international rules and jurisdictions cannot be trusted, and where
security and
defence of a liberal order still depends on the possession and
execution of
military force.[i]
One cannot help noticing
Kagan’s irony in
his caricature of European idealism. Kantian political
thinking is
powerless,
as it tries to extinguish all historical and real political
circumstances in an
illusory international state of peace between people and states, while
the
Americans are conscious of the historical moment in which one must act. The political field must renew
itself through exceptional acts of historical import and significance,
not
through feeble agreements, institutionalization of rights or
obligations
mutually recognized which only weaken the political power to act. The
state
must reserve for itself the right to exceptionality.
However, the political ideas
of American
neo-conservatism are not entirely new. They are based on a particular
tradition
in American philosophy stemming from Leo Strauss. Strauss emigrated
from
Germany to the US before the Second World War, established himself as a
philosopher and gradually gained an almost mythical standing in
political
circles.[ii]
One of the more well known Straussians, whose work has also been
translated
into Norwegian, is Allan Bloom. Paul Wolfowitz, who was central in
shaping the
US’s new security strategy, is a student of Bloom, and the books and
articles
written by Wolfowitz and others in the neoconservative circle are
crowded with
acknowledgements and expressions of gratitude both to Bloom and to
Strauss. The
fact that Leo Strauss himself had close relations to the German
philosopher of
right Carl Schmitt is perhaps lesser known. The latter was among the
most
prominent critics of the social democrat aspirations of the Weimar
Republic and
has been named the crown jurist of the Third Reich. His essays, with
their extreme
formulations and sharp analyses, are still fascinating to read.
In what follows, I shall give
an account
of Schmitt as a background figure to the neoconservative political
ideas and
rhetoric. Since the political thinking of Carl Schmitt cannot be
assumed to be
known in today’s political culture, we have to make room for a somewhat
thorough presentation of his concerns. Hence in the three first
paragraphs, I
shall portray Carl Schmitt’s intellectual horizon as a conservative
culture
critic and political thinker. In the following two paragraphs, I shall
elaborate on the relation between a Schmittian understanding of the
political
and the American neo-conservatism. In a concluding chapter, I shall
remind the
reader of the alternative understanding of philosophical modernism of
our
obligations towards cultural and political modernity in the tradition
from Kant
to Habermas.
Modernity
– an exhausted
project?
In the book Der
Begriff des Politischen (1932)[iii]Schmitt defines «the political» as
distinguishing between friend
and enemy: «The specific political
difference – accounting for political
acts and motives – is
the difference
between friend and enemy».[iv]
With sentences like this
one, Schmitt attempts to
convey the impression
of the
precarious nature of the situation political
beings are faced with. But
according to Schmitt, we have no direct access to the political as
such:
As
Heidegger poses the question of being anew in Sein und Zeit
(1927)[v],
Schmitt tries to pose
the question of political
being with equal
pathos:
«Our concern here is not fiction and normativity, but
the reality of
being
[Sic!] (die Seinsmäßige Wirklichkeit)
and the real possibility of the difference
in question».[vi]
But how does one delimit «the
political»
within a culture of modernity? And how does one justify
the sovereignty
of
politics as a kind of exceptionality? His answer to these questions
displays
Schmitt’s position as that of
a conservative critic of modernity. I
shall sum
up Schmitt’s concerns in
the following way: Starting
from (a) a
conservative
critique of modernity, he prepares the ground for
(b)a critique of
liberalism
and a reformulation of the relation between the political and the
natural
condition as described by
Hobbes.This
move allows Schmitt to (c) undermine the liberal justification
of
politics as
grounded in moral-practical autonomy, and rather present the political
as
sovereign in
an existential sense, i.e. as
a force beyond the
principles of a
rights-based democracy.[vii]
As
we shall see, these three
aspects of Schmitt’s political thinking
can be
recognized in the
ideological platform of the
neo-Conservatives.
(a) Cultural modernity can be
described as a
progressive process of differentiation where
scientific institutions,
morality,
law and art are separated, forming autonomous spheres of
value.[viii]
However, to Schmitt, the obligations and institutions of the Kantian
culture of
modernity entails a
significant impoverishment of the political sphere.
The
political can only
gain autonomy at the cost of neutralization:
«In an age of economy where the state no
longer claims
to know or to lead economic
affairs it must declare
itself
neutral with regard to political questions
and decisions. Thus it
denounces its
claim to rulership».[ix]
When political affairs are
increasingly arranged in
accordance with
formal
rules and procedures within a constitutional
democracy and bureaucracy,
the
political sphere looses its substantial meaning – its unity
is
threatened by
disintegration, what Weber termed «a god-strife between different
values
and
attitudes».[x]
In Römischer
Katholizismus und Politischer Form (1923)[xi]
Schmitt uses the Weberian analysis
to found a conservative
cultural
critique
which expresses a strong discontent with mass
culture’s tendencies
towards
dissolution. On the one hand, the division between state and
society
creates a
condition where the political is instrumentalized, becoming subject
to
strategic compromises between
various interests and organizations. The
technical-economical
thinking is common to both
capital interests and
the left
in their battle for the state. The social
democrat policy of
intervention is
only an addition to a liberal, parliamentary principle, according
to
which the
citizens possess certain rights towards the state.On the other hand, the aesthetication
of experience forced
by the
culture of the market – what Schmitt terms «aesthetic consumption»[xii]– a
general depoliticization of the state. The state looses its political
foundation while the citizens
are removed from the
political in the
arbitrary
whirligig of the sphere of consumption, where all things
are equivalent
and
exchangeable, and where everything can be given an aesthetic and
affective
value: «In modern economics
highly rational production is matched by
completely irrational
consumption. Any demand is
served by a
marvellously
rational mechanism – always with the
same gravity and precision,
whether it is
a demand for silk blouses or for poisonous gasses».[xiii]
Thus the Weberian analysis
of cultural modernity can be sharpened, and made to take a
more
conservative
course: The depolitized liberal state, lacking a fundamentally
political shape,
is
left over to the roulette of
interests and the meaningless enjoyment
of the
citizens. The response to
this situation, to Schmitt,
cannot be a
radicalization of the political autonomy of the citizens through
a
widening and
strengthening of democratic rights and liberties, since this autonomy
is the
root of
the problem. The levelling of
all differences contained in
Enlightenment’s idea of the political equality
of all is precisely the
source
of the impoverishment of the state’s identity and prepares the ground
for
a
strategic battle of interest between various organizations and
arbitrary
political movements.
Cultural and political
modernity cannot provide
its own foundation,
and its historical part is exhausted
in a thorough depolitization
of
the state
to the benefit of arbitrary power. In Schmitt’s
interpretation,
Mozart’s Die Zauberflute is an historical
document of how the abstract idea of
humanity must necessarily
express
itself
through the means of force, secrecy and privileged execution
of power.[xiv]
In the
book Die Geistesgeschichtliche Lage des
heutigen Parlamentarismus
(1923), Schmitt concludes
that the
concept of
«democracy» must be set apart from a liberal model:
«A
democratic state demonstrates its political power by knowing how to
keep back
the strange
and dissimilar which poses a
threat to its homogeneity
… Similarity
is only of interest and of value in
so far as it is substantial,
and
therefore
entails a risk of dissimilarity».[xv]
As against all kinds of
instrumentalized politics, Schmitt envisages a different and new form
of
political absolutism –
politics must regain its sovereignty
vis-à-vis other
spheres of cultural value in
order to provide an answer to
the
challenges of
the modern political condition, i.e. the threat
of a revolution, and
also to
give an answer to the general loss of
meaning which is a consequence
of a modern mass society in
which
social and
historical reality has changed into an
aesthetic consumption devoted
to
the
moment. As we shall see, American neo-Conservatives
remain bound to an
understanding of the political the intellectual roots of which are to
be found
in
a cultural critique à la Schmitt.
The myth of
«the political»
(b) The concept of «the
political» as understood by Schmitt is exclusively concerned with
political sovereignty. But
how can political sovereignty be interpreted
as
something other
than sovereignty of the
people – as expressive of
what Rousseau
termed the general will? How can
a sovereignty of a
personalist and
decisionist
kind be understood as political, rather than just
arbitrary despotism?In the book Politische Theologie (1922)
sovereignty is presented as follows:
«The sovereign is the one who
settles a state of emergency (über
den
Ausnahmezustand
entscheidet)».[xvi]The
state of emergency or the
exceptional thus becomes
the focus of the concept of
the political and
is
explicitly grounded in political sovereignty.This
different or exceptional
character of political power
lies behind
the understanding of the political as
a differentiation between
friends
and
enemies. Within a liberal frame of thought, the state of
emergency is
always a
permission made only in special cases in order to preserve the
constitution.
Within a liberal state in which power is divided, this exception does
not
enable a
one-sided politically
sovereign power to decide what
constitutes an
exception as well as to have
the mandate to secure the
constitution. To
Schmitt, on the other hand, the exception in itself implies
a
sovereignty which
incapacitates the idea of the liberal constitution: «The exception is
of
larger
interest than is the rule
… It confirms not only the
rule, but also the
existence of the rule, which
is exclusively derived from
the exception.
In the
exception real life breaks through the shell
of a mechanism stiffened
by pure
repetition».[xvii]
The turn towards a political
existentialism is apparent here. And this foundation makes
Schmitt’s
appeal to
early modern political philosophy very special. Schmitt’s relation to
Hobbes
was
an ambivalent one, in so far
as Hobbes revealed the modern concept
of the
political, while also
covering up its radical
character, and advanced a
liberal
model. As a founder of liberalism,
Hobbes defends a concept of
positive
law,
according to which the subjective rights of individuals
should be
secured from
the state.[xviii]
But,
to Schmitt, this is where the depolitization
and neutralization of the
state is
rooted: To Hobbes, the rational obligation towards the
sovereign
involves an
establishment of a state of law which also implies the singular
individual’s
right
to self-preservation. A weak
point in Hobbes’ model is that the
citizens
do not relate to the
ever-present possibility of
terror and destruction
within
the civilized liberal state – and hence are
not prepared to
sacrifice their
lives for the prevailing political sovereignty: «The state has
…
an
enormous permission: the option to go to war and hence rule over human
lives
openly. Jus
belli
contains such an
arrangement – it entails a twofold option: demanding a
preparedness to die
and
a preparedness to kill from those belonging to one’s own people, and
killing
people who belong
to the enemy».[xix]
This conclusion – an obvious break with Hobbes’ liberal
premises
– presumes,
however, a change in the concept of the state of nature. As commented
by
Leo
Strauss: «The political is a fundamental feature of human life;
politics
in this sense is destiny
itself; therefore man cannot
escape it.[xx]
The
political is no longer understood as a negation
of
the state of nature, but
rather as penetrated by it.
Schmitt’s interpretation of
Hobbes thus denounces a normative conception of right (rule of law)
from
the
start, in favour of a concept of the political articulating the
conditions of
human existence, la condition
humaine:
War, that is fighting
people’s preparedness to die … has no normative, but only
an
existential
meaning, admittedly in a situation of real fight against a real enemy,
not in
relation to some ideal
… There is no rational purpose, no right
norm or
exemplary program,
no beautiful social
ideal, no legitimacy or legality
to
justify the fact that people kill one
another for its sake.[xxi]
The foundational character
of the political lies not in the power of
persuasion Hobbes ascribed to
the state of nature through a
practical-pragmatic argument. The mutual obligation of the
sovereign
and the
citizen in the social agreement is
replaced by a concept of the political which is contained in
the idea
of the
human. In Politische Theologie any
political philosophy is played out against
a fundamental stance towards
the
presumably evil nature of man.[xxii]
Supported by
the contra-revolutionary
Catholic figure Donoso
Cortés, the dogma
of original sin is given an
original political
significance as the real
possibility of human evil can only be countered by a
sovereign opposing
force
which establishes order ex nihilo:
«Man’s blind
reason, weakness of will and incredibly forceful desire of the flesh
was to him
[i.e. Cortés]
blameworthy to such a degree that no words in the
human language
could
express the total
vileness of this creature … [A]ccording
to his
philosophy of history, the
victory of evil is an
unavoidable and
self-evident
fact, one which can only be prevented
by a miracle of God.»[xxiii]
To
Schmitt, the political can be understood as an authentic embracing of
evil and
chaos as a way
of existing, through a
decision to maintain oneself as a
human
and dangerous being. Thus it
becomes discernible how the
exceptional
– and
establishing a relation between friends and
enemies – becomes the
kernel of a
concept of political sovereignty transcending any
justification through
social
institutions or contracts: The sovereignty is tied to the
unpredictability
and
spontaneity of every exceptional case – any judgment and
employment of rules is
evidence for
an original act which cannot
itself be deduced from a
rule.
Rather, it is the other way around: A
unique facticity and
contingency
must
always be presupposed, an act which not only tests the norm,
but
invalidates
it: «In the independent meaning of the decision, the subject itself has
an
impact on
its meaning, regardless of
the question of content. What
matters to
the reality of legal life is
who decides».[xxiv]
This existentialist justification of the exceptionality of the
sovereign has
been embraced by Robert Kagan
and other neo-Conservatives. The
exaltation of
the singular
case contains the key to
understanding the political as an
existential mythos.
Political
theology of existence
(c) Schmitt’s founding of the
political in the relation between man’s existential state of nature
and
the
absoluteness of the sovereign seems very strained to a liberal, since
Hobbes’
state of nature is
a pre-political state, or,
alternatively, a
pragmatic
fiction representing the opposite of political life
as seen from the
inside of
political life itself. But the theme is apparent: the economic-liberal
culture
of modernity implies a
forgetfulness or repression of the political in
its
cultivation of the ideals of
liberal freedom, subjective
rights and
liberties
securing the independence, freedom of action
and political autonomy of
the
private individuals. Schmitt’s main point is that the political cannot
be
seen
as the complete opposite of the state of nature – as in the
liberal tradition
after Hobbes –
it is rather a permanent
possibility of chaos that
can only be
countered by a preservation
and consolidation of power.
From the point
of view
of the citizens this means that there is only
one exclusive standard to
political decisions – an authentic or an inauthentic way of
being. As a
political being one is faced
with an «either-or» situation where only
an embracing of the
human possibility of
political being
as historically and actually received, in anticipation of
man’s
utmost possibility, death or
destruction in the state of
nature.
The decisionist and
personalist concept of sovereignty is thus to be understood as
being
existentially justified and
delimited. But does it make sense in this
context
to call the sovereignty
a political one? Some
affinities between
Schmitt’s
basic idea and that of Heidegger allows us to
see this part of
Schmitt’s
approach more clearly. Heidegger, as we know, rejected the legitimacy
of modern
philosophy of the subject from Descartes to Kant with reference to its
repression of
the existential question of
being which should be worked
out
again in Sein und Zeit
(1927).[xxv]
Schmitt, for his part, aimed to disclose the existential foundation of
politics
–
as a possibility which
transcends the modern idea of
subjectivity and
freedom. Particularly
Heidegger’s analysis of human
subjectivity’s (Dasein) original ecstasy in relation to
its own
being – the
anticipation of death as a possibility
– refers the subject
to its real being, its given
possibility in being-there,
or Geworfenheit.
As against this background,
the existential motive in Schmitt’s political philosophy can be
seen
even more
clearly: Political sovereignty is a historically concrete and
monumental
possibility of
being, that of the
possibility of human order and
togetherness
in general. The political question of
being is directed towards an
original
transcendence in the political state – towards the
establishment
of a
sovereignty of a personalist kind, withdrawing any kind of internal
public
sovereignty. In Politische
Theologie this
figure is treated explicitly in analogy to the theological conception
of
God’s
simultaneous transcendence and immanent intervention in the world. The
existentialist
reference to the exceptional,
the breaking of rules as a
political category, thereby substantially
depends on a theological
figure,
God’s intervention from the outside through a miracle:
«The
exception in law is analogous
with a miracle in
theology».[xxvi]
As
with Heidegger, the world – and any kind of human order –
springs from an
original incident which
is historically concrete,
but also
transcendent.
Schmitt expresses this point by ascribing to sovereignty
in such an
event a
political character which gains its significance from a theologically
based
position. The state- and
contract theory of the Enlightenment, having
taken
part in what Weber
termed the process of
de-mystification of the
Western world
(Entzauberung der Welt), has
only
contributed to taming «the exception», in excluding it from immanent
constitutional thinking:
«The rationalism of the
Enlightenment rejected
the exception in any form».[xxvii]
Like
the rationalization of
nature into an ordered unity constituted by
mathematically articulated
regularities makes God’s
intervention
superfluous,
personal sovereignty is made superfluous
and replaced by legally
arranged
constitutional machinery: «The sovereign, who according to a
deistic
world
view … would have been the engineer behind the great machine,
has gradually
been pushed aside to a
radical degree. The machine is now self-driven».[xxviii]
Only
through mythologizing
the political is Schmitt able to replace the founding in politics in
the
autonomy of the citizens by
its existential sovereignty. To political
theology,
politics and law is no
longer one sphere of validity
among others. The
political is a foundational event of disclosure, one
that allows for
the
differentiation of culture in general: «The political unity is
essentially
the unity
which decides (maßgebende)
… It either exists or does not exist. When existing, it is the
highest
unity,
i.e. the decisive unity of the decisive case».[xxix]
Schmitt’s political thinking thus anticipates
an overcoming
of cultural modernity in the Kantian and Weberian sense.
The establishment of
the political as a «decisive
unity» renews an
archaic and mythical impulse by radicalizing the dogma
of original sin
and the
political decision which transcends a differentiated concept of
cultural
modernity.
But is Schmitt’s caricature
of the liberal justification for the autonomy of politics a pertinent
one? And
does his reference to the existential sovereignty of politics enable
him to
solve
the dilemmas he thinks
liberal constitutional thinking contains?
Schmitt’s concept of the
political is esoteric from
the start and fails
to take
account of the liberal tradition’s development
of the concept of
positive law
within the framework of a contract theory, nor the
commonsensical
justification
for the moral legitimacy of political law.[xxx]
Instead,
the contingency and facticity
it emphasised as a kind of
otherness or
difference, one that
to Schmitt establishes an antinomy
within the liberal justification of the state ruled by
justice: Since any
establishment of law must necessarily depart from a
moment
of facticity, i.e.
an actual
power
capable of sanctioning laws as something more than a merely moral
discourse,
the normative aspects of the law and the state will be suspended in
favour of
the decisionist privilege of
the sovereign. As we have seen, this
antinomy, to
Schmitt, can only
be solved by an affirmation
of political sovereignty
as an
existential condition, thereby
renouncing the idea of a
political
constitution
which is normatively founded.
The neo-Conservatives in the
US transpose
Schmitt’s solution to the same antinomy to
an international level, in
regarding
the political as a derivate of military force, rather than
as justified
through
the institutionalization and implementation of global rights.
Neoconservatism:
From Weimar to Washington
What does it mean to be
neoconservative? And what is
neoconservatism in an American
political context? It may
seem difficult
to
treat the various motives of neo-Conservatives together,
but a feature
most of
them have in common is a definition of their position as a political
anti-liberal
one and an emphasis on
restoring religious and national
virtues.[xxxi]
According to Kristol:
«The three pillars of modern
conservatism are
religion, nationalism and economic growth».[xxxii]
On the one hand, one endorses
the modernity of capitalist free trade,
while on
the other, being
critical towards the
liberating aspirations of
modernism when
it comes to art, interpersonal
relations, politics and
morality. I
shall
refrain from describing the neoconservative diagnosis of
culture and
society in
great detail, but merely give some brief comments on the context of
their
political views.[xxxiii]
In
the absence of an analysis of the consequences of capitalism to
the
impoverishment of work communities, interpersonal life and
symbolically
structured
self-interpretations (increasingly pressured by demands for
efficiency,
flexibility and
on-going change and
adaptation as a consequence of
free-floating capital, work restructuring,
new technology and an
increased
pressure for rationalization), the neo-Conservatives blame
the
intervention
policy of the welfare state and a nebulous «modernism» for the
dissolution of
values, divorce rates,
problems related to integration,
bad
performances in schools, a
polymorphous sexuality, the
dissolution of a
canon
in the universities etc.[xxxiv]
As
Himmelfarb states: «The
welfare state is responsible for a
separation
of morality and
welfare politics».[xxxv]
To the neo-Conservatives, the liberal policies of rights and welfare is
what
constitutes the problem (and the «class» of liberals and left
intellectuals who overload the
state’s legitimate ability to
social-political
compensation with their critical voices) – not the effects
of
transcending
market dynamics.[xxxvi]
It is
a fact that neoconservative cultural critique
sometimes allows us to
see some
worrying aspects of the dialectics of cultural modernity: To the
extent
that
the demand for self-realization and democratization of intimate
relations have
costs
with regard to obligations
towards concrete, moral others; to the
extent
that expressive,
aesthetic freedom appears in
the shape of narcissistic
varieties
of naivism and hedonism as
cynical strategies of
withdrawal,
conservative
cultural critique points to an inner logic in the
cultural ideals of
modernism
that threatens to undermine its own resources of meaning, i.e. the
symbolic and
narrative resources at the root of the character formation of the self.[xxxvii]
But
the main problem is that the
neo-Conservatives confuse the symptoms of
an
anomic culture with
cultural modernity as such.[xxxviii]
Thus, parts of the
neoconservative movement voice a
traditional conservative cultural critique à
la Schmitt –
an attack on
liberalism and social democracy as a mistaken policy which only
contributes
to
the dissolution of central patterns of value, and a neutralization of
the
state, leaving the floor open for
a battle between sectional
interests.
While
the individuals loose their dignity, inclination to work
and
self-respect by
becoming clients to bureaucratic welfare institutions, the state looses
its
sovereignty and its ability
to act to secure its self-maintenance.
Although the
last point may be seen
as a departure from the
general market
liberalist
thinking which is critical towards policies of
social intervention, it
is still
central to the general neoconservative critique of
liberalism.
«Neoconservatism», according to Kristol, «accepts the primacy of
politics to economy
without regrets».[xxxix]
This privileging of the political is intended to situate state
intervention
in
a context where maintenance and
preservation of the opposition between the state and civil
society is
the focus
of concern, as opposed to welfare state intervention, which tends
towards
letting
civil society dominate the
state in a policy of democratic
outbidding.[xl]
Cosmopolitan
despotism
The affinity between
American neoconservatism and Schmitt’s totalitarian state theory
and
practically apocalyptic
political vision may seem like an odd thing.
But, as we
have become
more accustomed to lately,
apocalyptic motives and
demonizing
distortions of political affairs
have become more commonplace
in the
rhetoric
of the American administration – as seen in
President Bush’s
speech of January
the 28th 2003: «[During] the new century the ideology of
power
and dominance has risen
again, trying to take hold of ultimate weapons
of
terror. And our country and
all our friends is once again
the only
thing
separating a world of peace from a world of chaos
and constant fear».[xli]
This
statement can be read
as being nothing but a statement of certain historical facts that
have
changed
since the cold war. But it is difficult to overlook the implications of
a
Schmittian understanding of
the sovereignty of politics as force and
power
relation between friends
and enemies. The picture of
the enemy gives
the
impression that one is subject to an
ever-present threat, and the
centre of a
sovereign power as a factor of integration is located in a
world of
friends –
in the power to act and to intervene on behalf of the self-maintenance
of the
state.
The liberal justification of
a sovereignty as a democratic and
constitutional product is toned down.
The tone of urgency in the
declarations of the Bush administration is a Schmittian one: A threat
of
existential chaos at once becomes a premise to the articulation of the
political as a
friend/enemy relation. This
rhetorical turn is no
arbitrary
reminder of Schmitt’s one-sided focus on
the political as a sovereign
decision
in the face of a surrounding contingent chaos, the concentration
of
politics as
military force – rather it is expressive of an intimate
connection between some
of
Schmitt’s original ideas and
influential Straussians in the American
administration. Of course, the
affinity between Schmitt’s
ideas and
neoconservatism in relation to foreign policy cannot be said
to
challenge the
constitutional traditions and ideas on which American democracy rests.
Neither
is neoconservatism «typically
American» – exceptionalism is an
idea
associated with people like
Kristol and Wolfowitz, which
is
contradicted by age
old American traditions of multilateral
obligations. Hence it is
important to
be aware of the circumstances behind the apparent success of
the
neo-Conservatives in setting constitutional and liberal principles
aside.
September 11th is
the moment of radical
contingency, giving
the
neo-Conservatives a horizon that makes their
decisions and
justifications
attractive as well as topical. As Ulrich Beck comments: «All of a
sudden
the anti-thesis of
neo-liberalism, the principle of the necessity of
the state
present everywhere, and in
its oldest, Hobbesian
variety – as a
guarantee of
security.»[xlii]
The
act of terror on September
11th reminded the
Americans of a
permanent possibility of an implosion of an existential state of
nature
as
intended by Schmitt and Strauss. It bears a frightening resemblance to
Strauss’
existential concept of war:
«The prospect of war is constitutive not
only
of the political as such … but
also of the prevailing moment
to
man.»[xliii]
Such
a high-strung rhetoric enjoys a
particularly favourable
climate for the
time
being, which may damage the legitimacy of
constitutional affairs as
well as undermine
US’ obligations to guarantee the principles of
international law and
human
rights.[xliv]
What are the practical
consequences of this state of affairs?The
contingent condition for the
credibility and resonance
of the
neo-Conservatives enables the definition of political sovereignty
through a
simple opposition: Security can only be gained through a sovereign
definition
of the threat
of terror as an inner and
outer enemy simultaneously. The
state
regenerates itself as
politically sovereign through
the establishment
of an
image of the enemy – something which cannot
be left to
international courts of
law or an international community of states. It is the task of the
state
to act
and to protect the prevailing political order, and this act is a
politically founding one, hence
it entails the
possibility, or necessity of overruling democratic rights and
liberties, such
as to
monitor telephones, e-mails
and electronic bank-services, to
allow for
the use of torture in
interrogations, doubtful
annulments of the status
and
claim for protection of war criminals,
judgments without proceeding
trials,
precautionary shootings of civilians, etc. In an
authentic endorsement
of
political «being-until-death» (terror) everyone is suspect from the
start
and must abandon their rights
as the price paid for security. In
a
neoconservative, resigned mood,
Irving Kristol spoke to the
same effect
20
years ago: «To demand ‘justice’ as a condition for political
or social
stability, means to make demands this world has never been able to
fulfil».[xlv]
This is
the logic inherited by the
Bush administration from Carl Schmitt and
Leo
Strauss, although its
condition is no longer that
of a clearly defined
enemy
and hence not in a war between states, but in
an ever-present, singular
threat of terror, the suicide
bomber who extinguishes himself in the
act itself.[xlvi]
Robert Kagan has the most
topical neoconservative interpretation of this historical
situation.
His
analyses make use of a simplified Nietzschesian psychology where the
political
is explained
in terms of relations of
strength and weakness: Only the
weak
advocate the validity of
positive international law,
the strong have no
need
for insurances of such a kind and need not appeal
to moral or juridical
ideas
to retain their hegemony. Right is nothing but a means for the
organization
of
an economy of commodities and for the regulation of a civil society. It
possesses no
unique dimension of moral and
practical validity; rather
it is a
«strategy of weakness».[xlvii]
Hence
an analysis of international
relations should be based uniquely
on the
ability to dominate by means
of military force, the
ability to
intervene to
retain one’s own position in a given inter-state constellation.
To
Kagan:
Understanding the
psychology of weakness is simple enough. A man equipped with a
knife
only might
judge a bear lurking around in the woods as a danger he has to tolerate
– since
attacking the bear with
a knife is considerably more dangerous than
lying low
and hoping the bear
will never attack.
However, the same man equipped
with a
rifle would judge differently as to what is
to count as an
intolerable
risk.[xlviii]
What is typical to Kagan is
the fact that the political and moral actor figuring in this
metaphor
never
recognizes his opponent as a dialogue partner, neither as a person nor
as a
concrete other,
but only as a potential
enemy, a dangerous bear. Hence
the
question of one’s relations in terms
of political and moral
dialogue
with one’s
co-citizens and with other states and their leaders is one
that cannot
even be
posed: There are no mutual obligations establishing normative bonds
between
the
parties – only the weaker party would use appeals to normativity
as a
rhetorical strategy.
A consistent feature in
Kagan’s analyses is the
lack of
differentiation between conviction
and persuasion – and
the best
kind of
persuasion is one that employs force: «In confronting real
or potential
opponents, the Americans prefer force to persuasion, emphasis on
sanctions
rather
than encouragements towards
better behaviour».[xlix]
Thus it becomes easy to discern
how diplomacy can be rendered
superfluous, and
how politics – rather than employing
feeble persuasion strategies
– should be
endorsed as a sovereign and exceptional power reality.
This
neoconservative
exceptionalism was given a geo-political breakthrough in Iraq.
Which
are the problems
associated with this analysis? To the extent that the claim that
the
«cosmopolitan despotism»[l]
of the US is intended to bomb so-called evil regimes into
a
liberal-democratic
modernity is a reliable one, the legitimacy of a war of aggression as
in Iraq
must
be established post
hoc. As
Habermas points out, the question of
legitimacy in this matter seems to
be decided the moment the
statue of
Saddam
Hussein falls off its pedestal. But despotic
humanism denies the
normative
dimension of this case: No admission into a
liberal-democratic
modernity can
take place without a preceding recognition of (1) the other’s
equality
as a
dialogue partner in a community of democratic states ruled by justice
(or at
least
an anticipation of such
equality) – which implies (2)
consensus between
free, democratic states on
how such a process of
democratization should
take
place. The first point involves an obligation
towards the otherness
of other cultures and traditions, which implies the
possibility of
alternative interpretations
of the premises of a
democracy of
rights; in short an admission of
the possibility of what
Ulrich Beck
has termed
«other modernities».[li]
The second point
implies obligations towards
international law and the
demand
for authorization through the
UN Security Council. We need
not discuss
in
detail all the fair alternatives to the
US’ unilateral intervention
– see for
instance Michael Walzer’s discussion[lii]
– it suffices to
assert that none
of
the existing attempts to justify the war have been sufficient. Neither
the
appeals
to previous resolutions, nor
the attempts to avoid the problem
by
indicating that Iraq was an
immediate threat, some of
which referred to
a
potential threat of terror, are very convincing.[liii]
The reference to Iraq’s
connections with terrorist groups, furthermore,
undermines the legitimacy
of attacking a state power,
since the threat
of
terror is singular and trans-national (hence it must
be fought by other
means
than traditional war between states). The neo-Conservatives,
however,
are
content with their assurance to themselves and the rest of the world of
the
exceptionality of
the moment – the
ability to act and to allow
for the
aesthetic self-justification of the success of the
victor. But, as
Habermas
concludes: «Let’s not entertain any illusions: America’s normative
authority
lies in ruins».[liv]
Normative
freedom and historical contingency
As we have seen, Schmitt
wanted to disclose a theological-existential concept of political
sovereignty
through a presentation of the normative aporia of liberal
constitutional
thinking. The
relation between an
established order of law and its
historical
possibility, to Schmitt, is based on
the paradox due to the fact
that
the
political must already be presupposed as a sovereign ground
of being to
the state and civil society. Kagan employs a
similar logic in raising the element
of contingency and historical
facticity to
the raison d’être of politics. To
Kagan, the old Europeans
are unable to solve the
normative paradox
presented by
the antinomy between the Kantian ideal of
a peaceful, cosmopolitan and
rights-based consensus and the guarantee of law (a potentially
despotic
state).
The US, however, solved this problem presented to the Kantian
continent:
«Europe’s new Kantian order
was able to flourish under the protection
of
an American power
performed in a Hobbesian
world. American power
enabled
Europeans to believe that power was
no longer necessary.»[lv]
Thus,
Europeans are unaware of the radicalism of contingency – and with
their
normative aspirations, they are at least unable to tame it.
But is this antinomy as
fateful to a concept of normative rights and freedom as Schmitt and
Kagan
would
want us to think? One should also ask whether their alternatives really
solve
the
normative paradox, or whether
they rather serve to strengthen it. Firstly, the
thought that
political
sovereignty escapes the arbitrariness assigned by Schmitt and the
neo-Conservatives to
the various interests and
diverse conceptions of
the good
in civil society is hardly convincing. Secondly, the
concept of the existential
contingency of the political state of nature, rather than being
as
«natural» or «original» as Schmitt and Strauss suggests –
is a postulated otherness or
difference vis-à-vis
the liberal order of law, retold as strategically constructed political
myths. Thirdly,
the
neoconservative caricature
of the liberal-juridical justification of the normative dimension of
politics
is not particularly apt – in Kant and in Ficthe, as well as later
in Cassirer
and Habermas,
the moment of facticity and
contingency is regarded as a
dimension of the concept of the political and
a premise to its
practical and
moral validity from the very beginning. Let us conclude by a
brief
discussion
of the three points (a)-(c).
(a) As to Schmitt, the
sovereign’s re-politicization of a neutralized political condition of
modernity
was
to overcome what Weber had
described as the «strife of
belief-power», i.e. the arbitrary weakening
of state power due to the
battle between sector interests and organizations. But, as has
been
pointed out
by several commentators, the normative antinomy is still a feature of
Schmitt’s
own endorsement of the
political – for who is to define the
relations between
friends and enemies,
and who represents the state,
and based on which
judgments
and interests? The arbitrariness in
the establishment of a
political
sovereignty and an elite transcending and conditioning the views
of
the
good of
the civil society – the aesthetic consumerism, according to
Schmitt – is also
at the root
of the political event.
Schmitt is struck by his own
critiques of
the aesthetic withdrawal and
private arbitrariness of the
romantics.[lvi]
(b) The myth of the state
can only be retained and confirmed through similar mythical images
of
the enemy
– which to Schmitt means the technical-instrumental modern
rationality as
Anti-Christ,
as illustrated by the Soviet
Union as an antithesis to the
West; a
re-theologizing of the foreign
political agenda in terms of
good and
evil
states, in the demonizing of other nations as enemies of
the historical
mission
of the good. The political myths are intended to depict the exception
and
the
contingency – and the exceptional character of political power
– in the
universal and
existential shape of the
myth: The force of myths is a
motivation
and an ever-present reminder of
the fragility of the
political state
and its
existential abyss. The problem with Hobbes’ myth of the state
in the
shape of
the biblical monster Leviathan was, to Schmitt, that the choice of a
mythical
figure was
a failure – as
Leviathan was defeated by the Jews and
the
Christians, the state was neutralized
and «conquered» by
particularist interests. Hence the political myth formation must be
stronger
than
the citizens’ struggle for
self-assertion and the tendency of the
civil
society to disengage from
the political.[lvii]
The problem connected with
political myths – whether it is re-theologizing of the political
through
the
doctrine of original sin, apocalyptic historical tales or national
myths about
privileged or
selected peoples or
demonizing images of the enemy
– is that they
are all ideologically
administered myths with a
strategic purpose. To
Schmitt,
the aim of the political myths was to
overcome the tendency to
aestheticism, to subjectification of the political, by
means of the original
force of the mythical images
and power to
disclose the
human in the convergence of
political sovereignty and
revelation. But
as
pointed out by Ernst Cassirer in his analyses of the return
of the
mythical in
the politics of the 20th
century, the force of myths no longer
consists in their power
of fate, i.e. in the
involvement of mythical
imagination in a ritual practice or mythical «form of life»,
but
rather in a manipulated effect. Thus, the sovereignty of the political
as a
mythical force is
necessarily paradoxical in
its rejection of
modernity, as it
must presuppose what it tries to transcend:
Our
modern political
myths are not in any way the products of a dark, mysterious power. They
do not
arise, more or less consciously, from a «national spirit». Rather,
they are intentionally invented for specific purposes … What we
have is a
completely rationalized myth.[lviii]
The antinomy of contingency
– the exception, the extreme case, the exceptional act etc.
which
is regarded
as constitutive of a constitutionally regulated normative freedom
– is itself a
contingency administered by
political elites.
(c) The element of
contingency within the liberal-juridical tradition does not lend itself
to
a
re-mythologizing of state power.[lix]
What characterizes the idealist tradition since Kant is
precisely the
attempts
to expound a concept of law and politics that allows for a concept
of
normative
freedom, while also viewing this freedom as existing from the start in
a
partially
contingent and real
social
and historical reality. In Kant this aim is already expressed in
the
justification for the
principle of law (Recht):
In the light of the inability of the capacity for moral
judgment to be
transposed to a real current normative order, we must presuppose
an external
law-giving instance that
implements a law-regulated relation between individuals who
pursue
their own
subjective aims and purposes separately.[lx]
We cannot go into the details of
Kant’s justification of the
principle
of law,
but it is important to see that the principle implies a change
of purpose
rather than an attempt to derive
the political from the moral.[lxi]
The political, to
Kant, cannot be derived from internal
moral resources – like the distinction between morality
and
legality, perfect and imperfect duties etc. – it must rather be
understood on
its own terms,
starting from a concept of
«external law-giving». The
legal principle (and the political as
external regulation of
freedom)
is,
however, justified through the self-limitation of practical
reason:
Within a
political order of law the power to execute right actions is
transferred from
the individuals
and their moral discourse to
a sanctioning authority,
which
thus replaces the moral-practical
discourse and practical
judgment in
an external (i.e. social) sense. The
contingent conditions of
this practicing of morality
are contained by a
principle of law that guarantees an actual performance
or completion of
normatively regulated relations (concerning the actors’ mutual
dependence as free
and equal – i.e. to the
extent that their
external freedom is a social reality). Hence a political order of
law
is
primarily a moral concern and acts as a filter to morally relevant
acts. The
practical-moral
validity of the principle of
law is reflected in its
universality and political equality of
justification.[lxii]
Thus there is an inner relation of legitimacy between the exercise of
the
principle
of law within a liberal
constitution and its moral aim: The
subjective rights and liberties of the
singular individual cannot be
imagined
without equally fundamental rights to political participation
(the
principle of
publicity etc.), continuously justifying the law-giving and political
authority.
State sovereignty stands in a
legal relation which is based
on the moral autonomy
and self-interpretation
of the citizens – and this relation cannot be thought of as
mutual
without
dissolution of law.[lxiii]
However,
a problem with Kant
is that the relation between morality and politics must be seen as
a
kind of
reflection of the idea of pure practical reason in a political
sovereignty.
Since Kant cannot
allow for any concrete or
institutional mediation of
moral
and legal-political discourses, other
than through the principle of
publicity,
there is always a risk of practical reason that the
political
sovereignty is
detached from the moral self-understanding of the citizens. The way in
which
the contingency of the state
ruled by justice is related to morality is
only
through a subjective
historical teleology: we must
presuppose that the
«invisible hand» of history gradually
arranges apparently
contingent
events in relation to a moral whole, a kingdom of freedom.
This situation, however, is
changed with Fichte and with the young Hegel. In the works of these
two
the
republican idea of freedom is developed in such a way as to mediate the
tension
between
morality and law from the
start. In Fichte’s Grundlage
des Naturrechts (1796)[lxiv]
subjective
rights (private law) are seen
as gained through
inter-subjective
forms of recognition, assigning external
guarantees of the individual’s autonomy and freedom:
I must
recognize the free essence of the other as
something else than myself as such, that is, I
must limit my own
freedom
through the possibility of the freedom of the other … the fact
that ach
limits his freedom through the
possibility of the other’s freedom … is in itself the
legal
relation (Rechtsverhältnis).[lxv]
Hence the autonomy of the
modern individual depends fundamentally on the intersubjective forms
of
recognition of the state ruled by justice, in which a post-traditional
concept
of freedom
and individuality gains
concrete institutionalized and
differentiated forms of expression. At the
same time the relation
between
subjective liberties and rights to participation is the reverse of that
of
a
Hobbesian individualism of property owners: Legal affairs and a
political order
are conceived of,
from the beginning, as
intersubjective guarantees of
the
self-reliance and normative autonomy of
the individuals. The
constitutional
principles of the state ruled by justice are external
manifestations
of
the
claim to autonomy and self-realization, admitting the vulnerability of
this
autonomy and the
need for external, i.e. real
social and institutional
criteria
for its performance. Thus the political rights
and rights to
participation are
fundamental to the performance and ascription of autonomy to
the
individuals
and imply an active regeneration of political legitimacy on the part of
the
civil
society: «Anyone who enters
the state must be capable of being
convinced that he cannot be
treated unjustly or
unlawfully. This
impossibility,
however, cannot exist unless the one who administer
the law can be made
accountable himself. A constitution in which the ones who
administers
public power
bear no such responsibility is despotic.[lxvi]
The
power held by the political and
legal state ruled by justice
towards
singular
individuals is only legitimate as an arrangement securing
the practical
applicability of the ideal of autonomy, so that the actual and
contingent
circumstances surrounding the
acting individuals can be seen to be
ordered in
relation to the aim
of freedom.[lxvii]
Thus political sovereignty
and positive law cannot be conceived independently of the
principle
of
continuous creation of legitimacy of the political sovereignty through
the
endorsement of the
citizens. This implies
constitutionally guaranteed
political
rights of participation, enabling the citizens
to influence the process
of
law-giving and decision through democratic procedures. But the
state
ruled by
justice cannot be assimilated to a concept of democratic self-rule, as
the
liberal constitution
and positive law is
principally different from and
primary
in relation to a purely moral-practical
discourse. The idea of a
state
ruled by
justice and a democratic constitution can be thought of as
a
prolongation of
the principle of law as a normative principle of recognition, balancing
the
relation
of law and morality. The
contingency and facticity of
political
sovereignty is continually shaped
through the participation and
active
lawgiving of the citizens – it is not, as in Kant, allotted to
a
practical
postulate to the view of history, rather it is subject to a striving
(Fichte) expressed through
the
civil society’s testing and creation of political legitimacy. The
constitutional and procedural rules
of democratic decision and
justification in
the state ruled by justice bring forth a mediation of law
and morality
which
reconciles the tension between facticity, contingency and
normative
validity.
Habermas elaborates the idea of a state ruled by justice in an intimate
relation to the concept
of a civil society which is
to provide the
institutional basis for a living democracy – while securing
the
expression of
the self-understanding of the citizens as discursively autonomous
beings in a
political reality:
The
legal order is
only autonomous in so far as … it guarantees an
institutionalized procedure
for
impartial opinion- and will formation, thereby securing the access of a
moral
form of rationality to
law and to politics. No law can be said to be
autonomous
without a realized democracy.[lxviii]
This normative mediation of
the facticity and contingency of the political – the tradition
from Kant
to
Habermas – is what Schmitt and the neo-Conservatives fail to
recognize. Their
hypostasis of
the political into an
almighty sovereignty –
administered by
political elites and retained through
mythical images –
rather
allows
contingency to be decisive to an understanding of political power.
The
fear of
radical contingency can only be mastered by embracing something even
more
frightening, an
all-encompassing political sovereignty. The exception
disenables the normative force
of the ideal of autonomy and
is
countered by the
political sovereign act which establishes order
by confirmation of the
exception, or by relying on the exception for its own existence. But,
as
Cassirer emphasized, the
alternative (i.e. a liberal constitution where
political sovereignty and
normative freedom are equally
foundational)
is no exhausted historical figure,
but rather a
normative
political idea which «must still pass its most difficult and deepest
historical test».[lxix]
The idea of a procedural and
just democracy – where contingency
and political
sovereignty
are subordinate to the
autonomy of the citizens – can
only be
realized in a cosmopolitan community
of states regulated by law.
Although the
realization of this idea is always preliminary, it is
nevertheless one
which is
guiding in practice.
[i] Robert Kagan: “Power and Weakness”. I Policy Review, juni, 2002, s. 1
[ii] I en
artikkel i nyhetsmagasinet Time
fra 1996 befinner Strauss seg på listen over de 25 mest
innflytelsesrike
personer i USA sammen med Bill Clinton, Bill Gates o.a.. Jf. Richard
Lacayo:
“Who has the Power?”. I Time, 17.
juni, 1996, s. 41.
[iii] Carl Schmitt: Der Begriff des
Politischen (1923). Dunker und Humboldt: Berlin,
1963.
[vii] Med
begrepet om “politisk suverenitet”
forstås altså en form for
politisk maktutøvelse og handling som er konsipert uavhengig av
opplysningstradisjonens idé om folkesuverenitet.Begrepet om
politisk
suverenitet har slik sett mye til felles med et post-modernistisk
begrep om
kunstens suverenitet. Og som vi skal se er det flere likhetspunkter
mellom
Schmitts tenkning omkring det politiske og et estetisk begrep om
suverenitet,
selv om Schmitt ønsket å unngå denne
sammenstillingen. Se f.eks Christoph
Menke: Die Souverenität der Kunst. Suhrkamp:
Frankfurt a. M., 1991.
[viii]Begriff
des Politishen, s. 71f. Dette
bildet svarer grovt sett til den kantianske differensieringen av
fornuften i en
erkjennelsesmessig, en moralsk og en estetisk dimensjon. Som Ernst
Cassirer
oppsummerer: “Området for ‘væren’ er
skarpt og klart avgrenset fra området for
‘plikt’; den verden som utgjør ‘natur’
står i motsetning til den verden som er
‘frihetens’. Mellom disse – både relatertog adskilt fra begge – finner vi
‘skjønnhetens’ område… Fornuftens
‘kosmos’, i sine inndelinger og enkeltheter, sin
universelle karakter og
systematiske struktur, avdekkes i denne treenigheten av teoretisk,
praktisk og
estetisk betydning”. Ernst Cassirer: The
Philosophy of Symbolic Forms – The Metaphysics of Symbolic Forms.
Volume four. Yale University
Press:
London, 1996, s. 3.
[ix] Carl Schmitt: “Das Zeitalter der
Neutralisierungen und Entpolitisierungen”. I Schmitt
(1923), s. 87.
[x] Max Weber: “Vitenskap som kall”. I Verdi og handling. Oversatt av Helge Jordheim. Pax
forlag: Oslo,
1999, s. 163. Videre heter det: “Demange
gamle guder – som har mistet sin magi og tatt
form av upersonlige
makter – står opp fra sine graver, prøver å
få kontroll over våre liv og
begynner igjen sin evige innbyrdes strid” (s. 163).
[xi] Carl
Schmitt: Römischer
Katholizisus und Politische Form. Klett-Cotta: Stuttgart,
1984.
[xx] Leo Strauss: “Anmerkungen zu Carl
Schmitt, Der Begriff des Politischen”. Sitert etter den engelske utgaven
“Comments on Carls
Schmitts Concept of the Political”. I Telos,
…., s. 740.
[xxx] Jf. Jürgen Habermas: “The Horrors of
Autonomy: Carl Schmitt in
English”. In The New Conservativism:
Cultural Criticism and the Historians’ debate. The MIT Press:
London, 1989,
s. 137f.
[xxxi] Jf. Jacob Weisberg: “The Familiy Way: How Irving
Kristol, Getrude
Himnmelfarb, and Bill Kristol Made Tormenting Liberals a Home
Industry”. I New Yorker, Oktober 21, 1996.
[xxxii] Irving
Kristol: “TheComing
‘Conservative Century’”.INeoconservativism – The
Autobiography of an Idea.The Free
Press: New York, 1995, s. 365.
[xxxiii] For en mer detaljert analyse, se Jürgen
Habermas: “Die Kulturkritik der Neokonservativen in den USA und
in der
Bundesrepublik”. I Die Neue
Unübersichtlichkeit. Suhrkamp: Frankfurt a. M., 1985, s. 30-56.
[xxxiv] Se
“TheComing ‘Conservative
Century’”, s. 366.
[xxxv] Sitert etter Weisberg: “The Family Way”, s.
187.
[xxxvi] Se Michael Walzer: “What’s Going On? –
Notes on the Right
Turn”.I Dissent,
vinter 1996, s. 5-11.
[xxxvii] Se f.eks. Richard Sennett: The
Corrosion of Character – Personal Consequences of Work in the New
Capitalism.
W. W. Norton and Company: New York, 1998.
[xxxix] Irving
Kristol: Reflections
of a Neoconservative. Basic Books: New York, 1983, s. xiii.
[xl] For en
diskusjon av den konservative og schmittianske
forståelsen
av statlig intervensjonisme og dens forhold til sivilsamfunnet i
kontrast til
en sosialdemokratisk forståelse, og problemenei denne sammenhengenmht. et
begrep om offentlighet og politisk legitimitet, se Jean L. Cohen og
Andrew
Arato: Civil Society and political Theory.
The MIT Press: London, 1994, s. 231-254.
[xli] “Presidentens tale om rikets tilstand”. I Morgenbladet – bilag om Irak-krisen, 14 mars, 2003,
s. 26-28.
[xlii] Ulrich Beck: Globalisering og
individualisering. Bind 3. Abstrakt forlag: Oslo, 2003, s. 140.
[l] Ulrich Beck: Globalisering og
individualisering, s. 172.
[li] Jf.
“Slik aner en allerede i dag at det i
fremtiden kan komme til å
eksistere mange moderniteter side om
side. Debattene om et asiatisk moderne, et kinesisk, et russisk,
søramerikansk,
og afrikansk moderne er bare i sin begynnelse. Slike diskurser
tydeliggjør at
det europeiske monopolet på modernitet definitivt er brutt i det
globale
risikosamfunnet. Slik sett fødes den radikale
modernitetskritikken i det
utenomeuropeiske rom av ‘eksessiv individualisme’, av tapet
av ‘kulturell
identitet og verdighet’, kort sagt av ‘McDonaldiseringen av
verden’, ikke som
simpel avvisning av det moderne, men snarere som forsøk på
å utforme og utprøve
andre moderniteter, som selektivt trekker veksel på modellen for
det vestlige
moderne”.Globalisering
og individualisering, s. 125.
[lii] Se f.eks:
“The Right Way”. I The
New York Review of Books, 13. mars, 2003.
[liii] Jf.
Thomas Assheuer; “Kriegim Irak
– Hat Bush Recht?”. I Die
Zeit, 16, 2003.
[lvi] Se
også John P. McCormick: Carl
Schmitt’s Critique of Liberalism. Cambridge University Press:
Cambridge,
1997, s. 300.
[lvii] For en
diskusjon av Schmitts forhold til politisk
mytedannelse, se
McCormick: Carl Schmitt’s Critique of
Liberalism, s. 270f.
[lviii] Ernst
Cassirer: Symbol, Myth
and Culture. Yale University Press: New Haven og London, 1979, s.
236.
[lix] For en kort
oppsummering av denne tradisjonens
røtter i tysk
idealisme, se Ernst Cassirer: “Die Idee der republikanischen
Verfassung. Rede zur Verfassungsfeier
am 11. August
1928”. I Dialektik 1. Felix Meiner
Verlag: Hamburg, 1995, s. 13-30. Se forøvrig Heinz Paetzold: Ernst Cassirer: Von Marburg Nach New York.
Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft: Darmstadt, 1995, s. 106f.
[lx]
Immanuel Kant: Metaphysische
Anfangsgründe der Rechtslehre (1797). Felix Meiner
Verlag: Hamburg, 1986, s. 219.
[lxi]Se bl.a.
diskusjonen i Robert Pippin: “On the Moral Foundations of
Kant’s
Rechtslehre”. I Idealism as Modernism. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge,
1997, s. 56-92.
Pippin ser helt riktig at Kants Rechtslehre
ikke bare angår “the normative issues of right, but … the
empirical
conditions that allow the exercise of rights” (s. 84). Problemet
med Pippins
redegjørelse er imidlertid at han fremdeles anser rettsplikter
som “a subset of
moral duties” (s. 64) noe som forhindrer at rettsprinsippets
egenart kan fremtre.
Som Wolgfang Kersting påpeker dreier det for Kant om en Standpunktwechsel som betrakter aktørenes frihet
og deres
handlinger fra et utenommoralsk ståsted hvor kun den enkeltes
utøvelse av sin
“ytre frihet” skal stemme overens med den andres
utøvelse av en slik frihet
under en allmenn lov: “Es ist aber möglich, von diesem
moralischen Standpunkt
abzusehen, es ist erlaubt, das Grundgesetz der reinen praktischen
Vernunft aus
einer außermoralischen Perspektive zu betrachten; und erst dieser
Standpunktwechsel
ist es, der vor das Rechtgesetz als solches bringt”. Wohlgeordnete
Freiheit. Suhrkamp: Frankfurt a. M., 1993, s. 126.
Selve ståstedet er imidlertid begrunnet med henvisning til
nødvendigheten av en
faktisk orden av normregulerte handlinger som speiler den praktiske
fornuftens
moralske gyldighetsdimensjon.
[lxii] Jf.
“Den handling er i overensstemmelse med rett
som i kraft av sin
maksime er slik at den enkeltes frihet (Freihet
der Willkür) er forenlig med alle andres frihet under en
allmenn lov”. Metaphysische
Anfangsgründe, s. 230.
[lxiii] Som
Cassirer understreker: “Die wahre
Souveränität, die der Staat aufzurichten und vertreten hat,
ist diese
Souveränität des Vernunftwillens”. Freiheit
und Form (1916). Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft: Hamburg, 2001,
s. 342.
[lxiv]
Johann Gotlieb Fichte: Grundlage des
Naturrechts (1796). Felix
Meiner Verlag: Hamburg, 1979.
[lxvii] For
Fichte er derfor statens idé i utgangspunktet
rettet mot sin
egen opphevelse – noe som ville innebære overgangen til en
ren moralsk
tilstand: “Die erste Entwicklung der Freiheit ist die, daß
der Staat als
willensbevegende Princip wegfällt. Er
geht darauf aus, sich aufzuheben,
denn sein letzes ziel ist die Sittlichkeit, diese aber hebt ihn
auf”. Das System der Rechtslehre (1812). Sitert
etter Cassirer: Freiheit und Form, s.
364. Riktignok ville en slik moralsk
tilstand være
“posthistorisk” i Kagans betydning, men for Fichte
uttrykker denne tilstanden
kun ideen som legitimerer statens hensiktsmessighet, noe som alltid
bare kan
ytre seg i en kontingent og historisk situert handlingskontekst hvor
statens
idé og frihetens idé forutsetter hverandre.
[lxviii]
Jürgen Habermas: Faktizität
und Geltung. Suhrkamp: Frankfurt a. M., 1992, s. 599. For en redgjørelse for Habermas’
forståelse av forholdet mellom rett
og demokrati, se min “Anerkjennelsens politikk”. I Agora 1, 1994, s. 22-44.